Language in the Ice Ages

When Did Europeans First Speak?

By: Philip G. Chase

Originally Published in 1992

View PDF

Using language is part of being human, and of all living species, we alone possess this ability. It is crucial to us because it underlies the way we deal with each other and with the world around us. The same must have been true in the past—but it is also certain that be¬fore some point in prehistory people lived either without language or with some less developed version of it, and that in consequence their lives must have been very different from ours.
Without language, things we take for granted would have been impos¬sible. People could not have passed on vital information such as, “There are fresh deer tracks on the other side of the ridge, and the berries there will he ripe in a few days. If no one has seen anything better, we should go there.” Without language, they could not have taught their chil¬dren that “You can ask him for help because he’s your father’s brother’s son, and a member of your clan,” and, without language, they could not have created the myths or expressed the beliefs that living peo¬ples use to define and enforce social values.

We are not sure just when it was that language appeared or when it began to play its crucial role in human life. Almost everyone agrees that by the Upper Paleolithic lan¬guage was a regular part of everyday life, but we are not so sure about the Lower and Middle Paleolithic. Lan¬guage is crucial, but it is also ephemeral. As soon as a word is ut¬tered, it disappears completely, leav¬ing no trace in the archaeological record. The only way it is preserved is through writing—and the earliest writing dates to millennia after the Ice Ages.
We archaeologists face a difficult task. We have to find out about lan¬guage, but we have no direct evi¬dence to work with. We thus have no choice but to search for indirect clues among the stones and bones of the archaeological record. What fol¬lows, then, is a detective story—al¬though the reader who likes a mys¬tery neatly solved in the last chapter will be disappointed. When it comes to the origins of language, there are many detectives with many ideas, but none of them has yet presented a jury-proof case. This is not for lack of effort So many scholars have written about the origins of language that a bibliography published in 1975 is it¬self two volumes long (Hewes 1975). The topic has attracted archaeolo¬gists, physical anthropologists, lin¬guists, psychologists, comparative cognitionists, semioticians, cultural anthropologists, ethologists, prima¬tologists, neurobiologists, and philosophers. Perhaps there is no consensus simply because there are so many experts with so many differ¬ent perspectives. Still, their work makes for interesting reading, and it is enlightening if not conclusive.

What Is Language?

Most animals communicate, but we are the only ones to do so with language. As we will see below, a few other species come close, but lan­guage is a very special and very human kind of communication.

In the first place, language is by its nature symbolic. That is, the connec­tion between a word and what it means is, almost always. arbitrary rather than natural. This is not true of the way animals communicate (Fig. I). The family cat hisses be­cause she is afraid and angry, and the family dog whimpers because the last time the cat hissed his nose got scratched. Both the hiss and the whimper are determined by genetics; they are natural and not arbitrary. Language is different. The word “dog” means dog purely by conven­tion, a convention that anyone speaking English must memorize. Other languages use different sounds to mean the same thing. No one is born knowing the words of a language—each must be learned. This puts a burden on our memory, but it also means we are not forced to make do with the few hisses and whimpers provided by our genes. In­stead, we can create words and can use them to talk about an almost infi­nite number of topics, things no dog or cat could ever discuss.

Language has another special property. It uses a mere handful of sounds for a huge number of words. Not all communication, not even all symbolic communication, works this way. A red traffic light and the word “stop” both mean the same thing, but the redness of the traffic light is a single unit; it cannot be broken down. The word “stop,” by contrast, is made up of four sounds that can be recombined to make at least five other words: “tops,” “pots,” “spot,” “opts,” and even “sopped.” This property makes language extremely flexible—a very few sounds produce an almost infinite number of sen­tences (Fig. 2).

Finally, language is governed by grammar, rules we all learn as chil­dren (even if our high school grammar teacher later makes us learn slightly different rules). Like words, grammatical rules are arbitrary. Thus, English makes heavy use of word order, while Latin relies more on changing suffixes. For example, “Julia loves Marcus” and “Marcus loves Julia” mean very different things; but in Latin, “Julia amat Mar­cum” and “Marcum amat Julia” both mean that Julia loves Marcus (with only a change in emphasis), while “Marcus amat Juliam” means the op­posite. What these rules do, though, is to let us use the grammatical con­nections between words to express the logical connections between the ideas those words stand for. Whether we are speaking English or Latin, we can make it clear who loves whom, and we need only a limited number of sounds and rules to do so.

These three properties are not the only ones that separate language from animal communication, but they are responsible for the crucial role language plays in our lives. They permit us to talk about what is pre­sent (“This meat is spoiled”), about what is not present (“There are deer on the other side of the hill”), about what lies in the past or the future (“The berries will be ripe in two days”), about what might be (“We won’t be able to fish if the pond freezes over”), about abstractions (“Persistence is as important as expe­rience when you’re trying to find deer”), or even about what is not (“The mammoth wouldn’t have es­caped if you had speared it in the chest instead of the hindquarters”).

These features of language are very abstract ones, but they do give us some idea where to look for clues about the origins of language. There are two broad categories of evidence available. Some scholars study mater­ial remains from the past: the ar­chaeological artifacts and the skeletal remains of Ice Age peoples. Others study living species, humans and non-humans, looking for clues to how language must have devel­oped. Each line of evidence has pro­vided information that complements the other. By combining all the strands, scholars hope eventually to come to some sound conclusions.

Apes and Language

Obviously, the first thing we need is some idea of exactly how far along the path to language our ancestors were when our lineage branched off from that of our nearest relatives. Be­cause this happened long before the Pleistocene, we can assume that if these ape-like ancestors had reached a certain linguistic level, then all our

Ice Age ancestors were also at least that far along. To help get an idea of what this level was, scientists have turned to our nearest living relatives, the great apes, particularly chim­panzees.

In the wild, apes communicate much like other mammals. They use sounds and gestures that, while not entirely stereotyped, are easily un­derstood in terms of the emotions that provoke them, and that show none of the arbitrariness of linguistic symbols. It is true that some monkeys do use something like symbols. On the basis of ingenious experiments in the field, two University of Penn­sylvania researchers, Cheney and Seyfarth, have shown that vervet monkeys have a basic repertoire of calls, a repertoire that is apparently genetically determined (1990). How­ever, they must learn the meaning of these calls. Young monkeys frequent­ly make mistakes, using, for example, the warning call for flying predators either when they see harmless birds or even when they see terrestrial predators. Moreover, Cheney and Seyfarth were able to show that the monkeys did not use such calls sim­ply as a by-product of their emotion­al state, but that they used them intentionally to influence the behav­ior of others. What they were unable to demonstrate, however, was that the monkeys were trying to change the ideas or knowledge (as opposed to the behavior) of other individuals, yet this intention is inherent in the use of language.

In captivity, chimpanzees and go­rillas have in fact been able to learn a rudimentary form of language. For decades, experimenters tried to teach apes to speak. They had no success until it occurred to Beatrice and Allen Gardener, a husband and wife research team, that the problem was not a lack of mental ability but rather that apes were physically un­able to reproduce the sounds of human speech. Using sign language, they were able to teach a now-famous chimpanzee named Washoe to make and understand words, and even to combine them into something re­sembling sentences. In fact, Washoe even made up names for things she had never seen before—she called ducks “water birds” and radishes “cry fruit” or “hurt fruit.” These experi­ments were repeated, not only with other chimpanzees and with gorillas (Fig. 3), but also with other lan­guages, including artificial ones where the words were symbols on a keyboard or plastic chips of different shapes and colors.

It would seem, then, that apes and monkeys do share with us the ability to use symbols. However, the num­ber of symbols any one animal learned was limited (Washoe learned slightly over a hundred), and there is considerable debate as to whether they ever learned any real grammar. Moreover, they never combined smaller units to form “words” in the way that humans do (although in fairness to the apes it must be admit­ted that no one ever asked them to do so; it may be that the natural calls of one kind of ape, gibbons, are con­structed in this way).

Thus, these are probably capacities that evolved during the past 5 million years rather than before, and one must remember that, whatever their capacities may be, chimpanzees living in the wild do not use symbols, much less grammar. Language plays no part in the way of life or mode of survival of any species but our own.

Language and Archaeology

It is therefore interesting that there is no solid evidence in the ar­chaeological record that symbols played an important role in human lifeways before the Upper Paleolith­ic. Starting about 35,000 years ago, we find abundant evidence of sym holism in Europe in the form of fig­urines, items of personal decoration such as beads, and signs engraved on rock (see the article by White in this issue). Before that time, by contrast, the evidence is so scanty as to be to­tally unreliable.

It is true that there are a few scat­tered items that are suggestive and—to the romantic mind—convincing. A skeptical mind will usually find more mundane and more likely ex­planations. For example, we have tens upon tens of thousands of frag­ments of animal bone bearing marks left by the stone tools of Middle Pale­olithic butchers. On a handful of these, the marks form patterns that catch the eye (Fig. 4). One could, if one so wished, interpret such pat­terns as “art.” But given the huge number of bones we have, the law of averages almost dictates that eye-catching patterns will occur now and then, even if the butchers had no in­tention of making art.

Some archaeologists believe they have evidence of religious ritual as early as the Middle Paleolithic. Reli­gion, of course, implies language, be­cause both language and religion make use of symbols and because language is needed to express reli­gious ideas. Yet the Middle Paleolith­ic evidence of religion is weak and open to more prosaic interpreta­tions. For example, there are appar­ent interments of bear skulls and strange juxtapositions of bear bones that have been interpreted as ves­tiges of an ancient bear cult. Yet these are probably the result of nat­ural geological processes having nothing at all to do with human ac­tivity (see Chase 1987). By the same token, what are thought to be bone whistles are almost certainly just deer toe bones punctured by the teeth of wolves or hyenas feeding on the “garbage” left at abandoned camps (Fig. 5).

Still, a few things from the Middle and even Lower Paleolithic are quite intriguing. Abraded lumps of ochre and similar materials demonstrate that people were using color before the Upper Paleolithic. We do not know, however, what they were using color for, or if its use had symbolic meaning. There are also occasional traces of butchering on human bones, indicative of cannibalism. Cannibalism need not be part of a ritual, though. Even in recent times cannibalism has probably more often been a desperate attempt to avoid

starvation rather than a religious act, and even chimpanzees have been guilty of cannibalism. Finally, there are a few human burials from the Middle Paleolithic, but burial by it­self does not necessarily indicate a system of religious beliefs. If burials were the only manifestation of reli­gion during tens or even hundreds of thousands of years in the entire Old World, then Middle Paleolithic religion was amazingly stagnant. It is much more likely that the dead were buried for emotional rather than symbolic reasons, to protect the body of a loved one from scavenging car­nivores.

Some scholars infer the existence of language before the Upper Pale­olithic from a subtler aspect of the archaeological record—the appar­ently standardized shapes of many stone tools. The logic is not always expressed explicitly, but there seems to be a belief that such standardiza­tion reflects mental categories that must have been defined linguistical­ly. That is, a flint worker had a con­cept matched by the word “den aciculate” (or some such word—no one claims it was English), and whenever he set out to make a “den­ticulate” the result was similar to all other “denticulates” he or his tribes­men made. But there are at least three problems with this argument. First, no one has demonstrated that the idea of a denticulate depends on the existence of the word “denticu­late.” Second, what archaeologists do when they study stone tools is to de­fine categories and then put all tools into one or another of them. Howev­er, just because an archaeologist can fit tools into categories of his own making does not mean that the pre­historic toolmaker had the same cat­egories in mind. Finally, much of what appears to us to be standardiza­tion is probably the result of more mundane factors such as the use for which the tools were intended, the materials from which they were made, or the degree of resharpening they underwent (Fig. 6).

All in all, then, the archaeological record provides little if any sound ev­idence for language or symbolism before the Upper Paleolithic. In all present-day societies, symbolism is so important that it inevitably finds ex­pression in the things people make. It would therefore seem reasonable to conclude that before about 35,000 or 40,000 years ago people did not use symbols to any significant extent, and that they, like chimpanzees, made do without language.

This may be wrong, though. Per­haps people used symbols in lan­guage long before they used them in a wider context. Peoples living today and those we know historically inter­pret their world or their emotions in religious or ideological terms and order their social lives by means of ritual. Our prehistoric ancestors probably could not have done so without expressing such ideas in sym­bolic artifacts. We must remember, however, that every other species manages very well without religion and ideology, and the same may have been true of earlier humans. From a purely theoretical point of view, then, we may be wrong to as­sume that a lack of symbolism in the archaeological record indicates an absence of language. In this case, we must turn to other kinds of evi­dence in our search for the origins of language .

Language and the Fossil Record

Language involves three biologi­cal systems. The first is the brain, where sentences are put together and deciphered; the second is the auditory system; and the third is the vocal tract. The first and last have provided further clues to the origins of language.

Not all parts of the brain are equally involved in the use and un­derstanding of language. To a con­siderable extent, linguistic functions are restricted to certain parts of the cerebral cortex (the outer surface of the brain, where most of the higher or more “intellectual” functions take place; Fig. 7). This localization of language shows up in certain details of the anatomy of the human brain—in a particular asymmetry and in details of the folding of the cortex. We cannot observe the evolu­tion of such anatomic details direct­ly, because no brains survive from the Paleolithic. However, there are skulls whose interiors we can study. To some extent, the shape of the brain leaves its mark on the brain-case (Fig. 8). Although the fit be­tween brain and skull is not tight enough to reveal all details, there is little doubt that the kind of asymme­try we see in the human brain appeared long before humans (of whatever species) migrated into Europe.

This should be conclusive evi­dence for language, but it is not. The problem is that functions other than language are governed by one side of the brain. In righthanded people, the left side of the brain controls both language and the use of the right hand. We know that our ances­tors had come to depend on tool­making and tool use very early on, and it may be that the asymmetry of their brains reflects not the use of language but the use of tools. In fact, by analyzing patterns of flaking on very early stone tools from Africa, an archaeologist named Nicholas Toth has found indications that their mak­ers were righthanded (1985).

Another form of evidence comes from what fossils can tell us about the vocal tract. According to linguist Philip Lieberman, human language is characterized by the production of specialized acoustical patterns, and this production depends upon cer­tain features of the anatomy of the vocal tract. These features are in turn reflected in the anatomy of the skeleton, particularly in something called basicranial flexion (Fig. 10).

Some scholars have taken this to mean that the absence of modern basicranial flexion reflects an ab­sence of language, something Lieb­erman himself denies. Language would have been possible without the anatomical specializations in question, but it would have been slower and more prone to misunder­standing. The real implication of Lieberman’s argument is that any fossil population with modern basi­cranial flexion had at least the po­tential for a fully modern form of language.

If Lieberman is right (and his work is highly controversial; see Fig. 9), then language in fully modern form may well predate the Upper Pa­leolithic and all reliable manifesta­tions of symbolism in the archaeo­logical record. While the classic Neanderthals of Europe did not have modern basicranial flexion, earlier specimens from Africa and Europe look quite modern in this respect.

This would serve to confirm what was said above, that symbols in artifacts and symbols in language may be very different phenomena. The fossil record may have more to say about language in the Ice Age than does the archaeological record.

Linguistics and the Evolution of Language

Strangely enough, those specializ­ing in the study of language have often been the least eager to discuss its origins. Maybe they are just more prudent than the rest of us. Still, a few linguists have been willing to speculate about language origins.

Recently, a number of scholars have attacked the problem using methods originally developed to study the ancestry of living languages such as English and of recently de­funct languages such as Latin. (See Allman 1990 or Wright 1991 for a layman’s review of this work.) They argue that all known languages had a single ancestor in the not too distant past (a finding that would also sup­port a recent origin for all modern humans). However, it is not clear that their methods are reliable over such huge amounts of time. Links that can be made with confidence between languages still spoken today are more tenuous when they are made between the reconstructed an­cestors of the reconstructed ances­tors of living languages. This is—and will continue to be—a subject of live­ly debate among linguists.

Moreover, linguists disagree about whether language evolved gradually or suddenly. Some of them are im­pressed by the complexity of lan­guage and argue that it could not possibly have sprung up suddenly and fully developed. Others, by con­trast, are more impressed by a simi­larity in underlying structure among all languages and by the interdepen­dence of all aspects of a language. These linguists argue that language could not have developed piecemeal but must have arisen (quite rapidly) as a single genetically determined neurological change.

An alternate possibility is that lan­guage developed in a series of fits and starts. Language is not necessari­ ly a single system, an all-or-nothing phenomenon. We have already seen that living apes can use language-like symbols. It is quite possible, as lin­guist Derek Bickerton points out, that our early ancestors used such symbols much as trained apes do, more or less without grammar (1981). This would have limited the usefulness of language, but even without grammar, words would have been useful. Grammar might have developed later, perhaps in stages. Testing such a notion is not simple, however, and for the next few years at least, it seems that linguists will continue to disagree on this question.

Interpreting the Indirect Evidence

I warned the reader at the begin­ning of this article that there was no certainty about when language origi­nated. Specialists agree on only one point: by the Upper Paleolithic peo­ple were fully modern in biology and similar to living hunter-gatherers in terms of behavior. The symbolism evi dents in their art makes it clear that their linguistic abilities were as high­ly developed as our own.

For earlier time periods there is no such agreement, nor is there like­ly to be for a long time. So many kinds of evidence are relevant that no one person can possibly under­stand and evaluate them all. A com­petent neuroanatomist will probably have a naive or incomplete under­standing of the archaeological evi­dence, and vice versa. Even among specialists in the same field, however, there is as much disagreement as agreement. This is probably in­evitable. We have, after all, no direct evidence: every word uttered in Ice Age Europe is gone forever. Nor can we fall back on the scientist’s main tool, experiment. With nothing but indirect evidence, we must rely heav­ily on complicated chains of reason­ing—a sure formula for disagree­ment.

I will nevertheless venture a guess, but only on the condition that I have the right to change my mind in the future. I am skeptical that the first symbols in the archaeological record mark the beginnings of language, so it may be that language originated before the Upper Paleolithic. There are two reasons for my skepticism. It seems to me that archaeologists have been overly impressed by the fact that the first good evidence for sym­bolism appears in Europe about the same time as both anatomically mod­ern Homo sapiens and some rather striking technological changes. Seen in a world-wide perspective, art and symbolism actually appear in widely separated parts of the world at very different times, without any apparent connection to biological change. This would imply, since there is cer­tainly a biological basis to language that at least in some places people were using symbols in language be­fore they treated their artifacts as symbols.

Thus Middle Paleolithic life in Eu­rope may in some ways have been more sophisticated than the artifacts alone would lead us to believe, with people exchanging information and ideas much as they do today. Yet in other ways it must have been very dif­ferent from life in later times, since some aspects of intellectual life that we living humans take for granted would have been absent or at best rudimentary. This presents an inter­esting new problem. If art, religion, and the like postdate the origin of

language, then they did not appear automatically as soon as people began to create and use symbols. Why, then, did they develop, and what must life have been like among fully linguistic people without art or religion?

In any case, however inconclusive or unsatisfactory our understanding of the origins of language, it is a good illustration of something all sci­entists are aware of: the more we learn, the more questions confront us. Certainly the topic is one that will remain controversial and interesting for a long time, and with no lack of surprises still in store.

Cite This Article

Chase, Philip G.. "Language in the Ice Ages." Expedition Magazine 34, no. 3 (November, 1992): -. Accessed April 30, 2024. https://www.penn.museum/sites/expedition/language-in-the-ice-ages/


This digitized article is presented here as a historical reference and may not reflect the current views of the Penn Museum.

Report problems and issues to digitalmedia@pennmuseum.org.